in

Determinism

Determinism

The abstract noun functions like a family name for a group of philosophical doc­trines each of which asserts that, in one sense or another, events occur of necessity when and as they do. Different members of the family stake out different doctrinal territories, some construing the necessity involved in purely logical terms, some in causal terms, and still others in terms of predict­ability. Each has to do with necessary connections between past, present, and future.

Much confusion can arise from failing to distin­guish one member from another. Much more can arise when they are taken to be identical with, or somehow allied with, other, less defensible doc­trines: and predestination, for example. And still further confusion can arise when one or the other is taken to imperil such cherished beliefs as that in our own . It is important, therefore, to sort out the differences between them. We need to comply with the philosophical maxim, “Be care­ful with concepts and the words in which we express them.” Sadly, there are some who bandy about the terms determinism and deterministic—often using them as terms of abuse—without saying exactly what they mean by them.

Three main members of the determinist family call for careful attention. The most basic is logical determinism, which asserts that future events (i.e., changes in states of affairs), like past events, are determinate and that statements about them are determinately true or false. It claims that if a state­ment about the future is true, then of necessity the events it is about will occur. It claims that the future will be what it will be, just as the past was what it was. These claims are evident tautologies. Yet, despite its evident logical credentials, this version of determinism has been called into question, often on the grounds that it seems to imply fatalism.

The term determinism is usually taken to refer to the doctrine of causal determinism. This holds that future events are caused by, determined by, or necessitated by, present ones and that these, in turn, are caused by past ones. It holds that nothing happens by “pure” chance. Causal determinism is an ontological doctrine: It makes claims about the contents and character of reality, holding that events that occur within it are connected in a temporal chain of cause and effect.

Unfortunately, causal determinism is often con­fused with predictive determinism, the view that if one knew in precise detail what events and states of affairs had occurred in the past, one could thereby predict present and future events and states of affairs. The 18th-century French mathematician and astronomer Marquis Pierre-Simon de Laplace (1749-1827) couched his concept of determinism in these terms, envisaging a hypothetical intelli­gence so vast that its knowledge of the laws of nature and the precise state of the universe at any given time would enable it to predict any future state of the universe with complete precision. Yet it is clear that this version of determinism adds an epistemic claim (a claim about our knowability of the world) to the ontological claim made by causal determinism. They are by no means identical.

Predictive determinism presupposes the of causal determinism, and that, in turn, presupposes the of logical determinism.

Logical Determinism

Logical determinists are committed to a realist account of truth. A statement is true if and only if reality is as the statement says it is. A statement’s truth or falsity, therefore, does not depend on our perceptions or conceptions of reality, let alone on our knowledge (or lack of knowledge) of reality. By definition, there is only one reality (only one world), though there are many different concep­tions of it. It is by virtue of this “correspondence” between true statements and the way the world is that logic gets its grip on reality. Hence the philoso­pher Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951) claimed that logic is not just a body of human-made doc­trine but is a “mirror image” of the world.

Logical determinists insist that the laws of logic apply to all statements, including statements about the future, for example, “A huge asteroid will destroy the earth in the year 2020.” Logical deter- minists hold that the law of dentity (if P then P) shows that necessarily if this event is going to occur in 2020 then it will occur at that time; that the law of excluded middle (either P or not-P) shows that necessarily it will either occur or not occur in 2020; and that the law of noncontradiction (not both P and not-P) shows that it is impossible for it both to occur and not to occur in 2020.

Objections to Logical Determinism

Some people would object to the claim, on which the realist theory of truth is based, that there is only one reality. Such an objection is fostered by post­modernist and relativist claims about each of us having his or her “own” reality and, hence, that there are many different realities. It is doubtful, however, whether this sort of talk can be translated without loss of meaning into talk of many different conceptions or beliefs about the single reality that comprises all that was, is, or will be, the case.

Others would object to the realist account of truth, professing themselves to be deeply puzzled by the notion that true statements “correspond with” reality. But truth need not be explained in terms of correspondence. It suffices to say that a statement has the property of being true just when things are as it says they are. That formulation seems much less mysterious, as it focuses on the conditions in which a statement is true as opposed to wrestling with the abstract question, “What is truth?” It lets us understand what truth is by con­centrating on our use of the predicate is true rather than on the abstract noun truth. The conditions under which a statement has the property of being true are different from the conditions under which we can know a statement to be true. Truth is not the same as verification (knowledge of truth). If it were, it would be absurd to suppose that there are undiscovered truths about the universe, awaiting discovery in such realms as the natural sciences, mathematics, or logic. It would be to suppose that we already know all the truths there are to know.

The notion that logic is a reflection of the basic structure of reality has also come under attack by those who suppose logic to be nothing more than a human-made doctrine about relationships between statements in human language. There isn’t just one logic, they say, but many. We can invent new logical notations, including ones that abandon such traditional laws as the law of excluded middle. That “law” allows only two truth-values (being determinately true and being determinately false) with no allowance for inter­mediate truth-values. Hence, to escape from the threat of fatalism that logical determinism poses in the minds of many, some logicians have devised three-valued logics, allowing a statement to be neither determinately true nor determinately false but, in some sense or other, “indeterminate.”

Formal systems for these and other multivalued logics can indeed be devised. But the question then arises as to the precise meaning to be attached to “indeterminate.” In what sense of the word should we describe the statement that an asteroid will destroy the earth in 2020 as indeterminate? Can “indeterminate” coherently be understood as mean­ing anything other than “not known to be true or known to be false”? If not, then a defender of the law of excluded middle can reply that the propo­nent of these alternative logics is confusing truth and falsity with our knowledge of truth and falsity.

Similar questions can be asked about the pro­posal that we should adopt some nonclassical logic to handle problems in quantum theory. Is quan­tum “indeterminacy” to be construed in terms of anything more than a failure of our attempts to ascertain what the determinate state of a quantum system happens to be at a single point of time?

Causal Determinism

Logical determinists stake their claim on the truths of logic: truths that are said to be truths of reason, truths that we can come to know a priori, that is, without needing to appeal to experience. By way of contrast, causal determinism—roughly, the claim that the causal principle, “Every event has a cause”—makes a claim that we can certify, if at all, only empirically, that is, only by appeal to experience.

But is causal determinism in fact true? Certainly our everyday experience suggests so. “Things don’t just happen,” we say, meaning that things don’t happen by so-called pure chance. Science, as commonly conceived, is the investigation of the unknown causes of various kinds of phenomena: the causes of asteroid collisions, the causes of global warming, the causes of physical and mental illnesses, and so on. That is to say, scientists try to discover hitherto unknown general truths (laws of nature) about how the universe works.

In principle the laws of nature seem to apply universally: not just to inanimate objects but to animate ones as well, including human beings. The more we discover about the mechanisms that make our bodies and minds work as they do, the more our behavior yields to explanation in terms of the interplay of a complex network of causes. Can all our behavior, mental as well as physical, be so explained? Are we just a product of nature and nurture? What are we to make of free will?

Belief in the universal reign of came under threat during the early 1900s with the development of quantum mechanics, the study of the behavior of the elementary constituents of the physical universe. The Danish physicist Niels Bohr had initially conceived of atoms as being like miniature solar systems, each with electrons spinning around a central nucleus in much the same way as the planets and asteroids revolve around the sun. But whereas in the case of the planets and asteroids about which, ever since Johannes Kepler and Isaac Newton, we have been able to formulate causal laws governing their behavior, in the case of electrons supposedly “spinning” around the atomic nucleus, we have not. Quantum theory, it turns out, does not yield strict causal laws about the behavior of the “ulti­mate” constituents of the universe. At best it yields only probabilistic estimates of how they will behave. Does this show that causal determin­ism is false? Or doesn’t it?

Objections to Causal Determinism

Many thinkers think that the doctrine of causal determinism imperils the idea that we have free will. Indeed, it is often simply taken for granted, by those who haven’t thought carefully about what “free will” means, that the two are logically incompatible. How can one be free, it is asked, if everything one does is determined by causes lying in the past? We cannot make the past other than it is. So if our present and future actions are neces­sitated by past causes, we cannot be free to do anything other than what those causes dictate that we will do. But we are free. Therefore, our free actions cannot be caused. So goes the argument of those subscribing to the libertarian’s so-called contra-causal account of free will.

Some determinists agree with the libertarians that the ideas of free will and causal determinism are incompatible. But far from concluding that the doctrine of causal determinism must give way, they conclude that it is our beliefs in free will and responsibility that have to be abandoned. No one is ever really free or really responsible, they say. From their perspective, criminals deserve therapy and treatment, not blame and punishment. Such determinists are known as hard determinists.

Many philosophers, however, say that both the libertarians and the hard determinists have given a mistaken account of the conditions in which we are held to be free and responsible. On an alternative account, a person is free to act (roughly speaking) if he or she acts as he or she chooses, and does so with­out constraint or impediment. Only in those condi­tions can we properly hold people responsible. Such philosophers are known as compatibilists. Many well-known philosophers—John Locke, David Hume, J. S. Mill, F. H. Bradley, Bertrand Russell, Moritz Schlick, and A. J. Ayer, for example—have taken this position. A compatibilist can regard the question whether causal determinism is true or false as an open one, one that may yet be settled by fur­ther empirical inquiry. Some compatibilists, however, stick to their belief in universal causality. They are known as soft determinists.

Given this range of well-argued positions taken by philosophers on the issue of free will, it is naive to simply assume—as so many people do—that there are only two alternatives in the dispute: belief in causal determinism, on the one hand, and belief in free will, on the other.

Sadly, even sophisticated thinkers from disci­plines outside may share this simplistic assumption. One of the founders of quantum phys­ics, Werner Heisenberg, claimed that his newly discovered principle of indeterminacy opened the door for a belief in free will. How a lack of causal­ity at the quantum level could be identified with responsibility-conferring freedom, he did not explain. Nor did he explain how we can be respon­sible for choices that occur, not from causal neces­sity, but just by sheer chance. The notions of freedom and responsibility seem as out of place in a wholly indeterministic universe as they seem to be in a deterministic one. Little wonder that compati- bilists insist that these notions, when carefully ana­lyzed, turn out to be compatible with both.

Predictive Determinism

Whether or not causal determinism is true, and whether its truth or falsity can in principle be established by quantum physics, one thing is clear: Current quantum theory does not enable us to make precise predictions about what is going on at the quantum, or subatomic, level of reality.

What, if anything, does this imply about the belief in universal causality? Remember that predic­tive determinism adds an epistemic thesis to the ontological thesis of causal determinism. This means that predictive determinism could prove to be false without causal determinism also being false. Albert Einstein’s lifelong critique of quantum theory capi­talized on this purely logical point. From our inabil­ity to measure the precise states of elementary particles, he argued, it does not follow either that they don’t have determinate states or that those states are not determined by previous states.

Will physicists who are as philosophically well read and conceptually astute as Einstein eventually conclude that quantum physics provides a conclu­sive refutation of the ordinary belief in causality? Or will some future theory find a way of reinstat­ing it? Perhaps time will tell.

Raymond Dynevor Bradley

See also Causality; Fatalism; Hume, David; Laplace,

Marquis Pierre-Simon de; Predestination; Predeterminism; Quantum Mechanics; Russell, Bertrand; Time, End of

Further Readings

Bradley, R. D. (1962). Determinism or indeterminism in microphysics. British Journal for the , 13, 51.

Bradley, R. D. (1963). Causality, fatalism, and morality. Mind, October.

Bradley, R. D. (1974). The causal principle. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 4(1).

Hook, S. (Ed.). (1958). Determinism and freedom in the age of modern science. New York: Macmillan.

Stebbing, L. S. (1937). Philosophy and the physicists. London: Penguin.

Van Inwagen, P. (1983). An essay on free will. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

What do you think?

Destiny

Destiny

Devils - Demons

Devils (Demons)